Health and nutrition quackery, relabeled in the past ten years or so as
DISTINCTIONS BETWEEN “ALTERNATIVE” AND SCIENTIFIC MEDICINE
Probably the most dramatic difference between “alternative” and scientific medicine is that “alternative” medicine relies in large part on testimonials and subjective reports and “feelings” of patients and therapists to validate therapeutic effectiveness. In other words, if a patient simply reports that therapy X has really made them better, this is accepted as proof that therapy X really has made the patient better. As noted in chapter 10, testimonials are an extraordinarily unreliable source of evidence for the reality of a cure. Just remember all the urine drinkers happily and, in their own minds, honestly stating that drinking their own urine cured them of this, that, or the other disease. In addition, “alternative” medicine proponents often actively deride the importance of carefully controlled scientific studies of whether a therapy actually works. Mehl-Madrona (1997) objects to rationally in general, saying “rational explanations are destroying medicine today.”
One of the most famous proponents of “alternative” medicine is Dr. Andrew Weil, author of several books on the topic (Weil 1995a, 1995b, 1997, 1998) that, among other things, exemplify the importance that unsupported testimonials and anecdotes have in alternative medicine. As Relman (1998, 2000) points out in a through critique of Weil’s views, Weil accepts as evidence reports of cures where not only is there no documentation that the patient was cured, there’s no documentation that the patients was even sick in the first place! In one case, reported in Weil (1997), an individual wrote Weil and said he had been diagnosed with “bone cancer.” He went on to say that he cured himself by riding a bicycle and eating healthy foods. Nowhere did he provide Weil with the slightest evidence for his illness—and yet Weil reports this “case” as proof that a good diet can cure cancer!
The approach of scientific medicine to the issue of how to determine whether a therapy works or not is totally different. Scientists in all fields of investigation have long known that the world is much too complex to be understood on the basis of subjective impressions, beliefs, and feelings. Rather, careful and sometimes tedious procedures have to be followed to tease apart the welter of interrelationships that lead to cause-and-effect understanding. This is especially true when dealing with issues of therapeutic effectiveness, where the subjective result of the therapy may be very different than the actual result.
There are several factors that work to convince both patient and therapist alike that an ineffective therapy has actually worked. The best known of these is the
Placebo effects can be due to a number of factors (see Shapiro and Shapiro 1997, for a review) having to do with the patient, therapist, or evaluator. This is fairly easy to see, even for purely medical treatments. As a hypothetical example, consider a new drug treatment for Parkinson’s disease, a degenerative brain disease seen mostly in the elderly, the major symptoms of which are difficulty in movement and a tremor. Further assume that the new drug has no real effect whatsoever on the disease, but that the promoter of the new drug is a charismatic individual who truly believes in its effectiveness. Believing strongly, he sees no reason to waste time with a placebo-controlled study. Rather, he simply gives the drug to a group of Parkinsonian patients for, say, six months, and sees if they have improved at the end of that period. He will almost certainly find improvement. Why? His patients will have been told, repeatedly, that they are getting a new and effective treatment. They will be excited. They will be more motivated to try hard on the various tests administered to them. Their evaluators, perhaps the therapist himself, will likewise be motivated to see improvement. Further, Parkinson’s disease, like any disease, fluctuates over time. Patients are a little better one day, worse the next, better a week later, and so on. The therapist and the patient, believing in the (yet unproven) effectiveness of the new drug, will interpret random improvements as a result of the drug, while ignoring deteriorations. This is exactly the same kind of selective memory that is responsible for belief in prophetic dreams and hunches noted in chapter 2. Unfortunately, the history of medicine is littered with stories of worthless therapies, some very harmful, that were sincerely believed by practitioners to be effective until double-blind, placebo-controlled studies proved otherwise.
A somewhat less well known effect that can lead to unwarranted beliefs in therapeutic effectiveness is a statistical artifact called