obscured or permit ed inequality, had
reflected and furthered it both, was seen not as a reason that
law should be disregarded but as a reason it had to be used.
This was not done out of political naivete or civics-class faith
in the legal system’s intrinsic justice. It was done out of determination to make this society’s normal everyday mechanisms work for normal everyday people—all of them. Civil rights is
a “Look, we live here, too” movement. It is not dedicated primarily to making the society more comfortable for outlaws or to lessening the stigma of marginality or to making powerlessness feel bet er. It is dedicated to changing basic norms so that what was outlaw and marginal and powerless no longer is. It
aims to alter the mainstream. For civil-rights movements,
then, the fact that law is an instrument of the powerful has
never been an inert fact to be met with complacency or
despair, far less a reason to leave its power in the hands of the
powerful. It has been a reason that the law cannot af ord to
be ignored. The law’s pretense at providing equal justice did
not provide an occasion for cynicism, but a hypocrisy to be
exposed and a promise to be delivered, not a radical reason
to do nothing. The law of sex discrimination, aimed at altering the inequality of women to men, at eliminating the subordination of women to men
The civil-rights approach to pornography is an application
of this tradition, this analysis, and this determination to the
emergency of pornography and the condition of women. Accordingly, the antipornography civil-rights law (“the Ordinance”) does not admonish or moralize or apologize or request. By making it possible for women who can prove harm Pornography and Civil Rights
29
to sue pornographers, it draws a line by making action
possible. In so doing, it defines a standard that tells the pornographers and their consumers that women are human beings, meaning that when they are hurt, something can be
done about it. Unlike any prior approach to pornography,
this law is based on proof of a harm, not a judgment about the
permissibility of an idea. And, like al civil-rights legislation,
it addresses a harm that derives its meaning and sting from
group status.
30
Pornography and Civil Rights
The Ordinance
Statement of Policy
The statement of policy that begins the Minneapolis Ordinance capsulizes its legal approach: Pornography is sex discrimination. It exists in Minneapolis posing a substantial threat to the health, safety, peace, welfare, and equality of citizens in the community. Existing state and federal laws are inadequate to solve these problems in Minneapolis.
Pornography is recognized as a practice of civil inequality
on the basis of gender, posing the threats to its target population that al socially institutionalized inequalities do. This clause also recognizes the obvious fact that, while many of the
acts that make up the distinctive harms of pornography are
formally illegal, no existing laws are effective against them. If
they were, pornography would not flourish as it does, and its
victims would not be victimized through it as they are. Lawyers
seeking to protect pornography often become extremely ingenious in inventing legal theories that they insist already cover all serious harms of pornography—legal theories they
seldom intend to try to make work, by the way.