articulatory choreography, the only way to keep up the speed of communication was to cut corners. Rather than produce every phoneme as a separate, distinct element (as a simple computer modem would), our speech system starts preparing sound number two while it’s still working on sound number one. Thus, before I start uttering the
This dance keeps the speed up, but it requires a lot of practice and can complicate the interpretation of the message.[31] What’s good for muscle control isn’t necessarily good for a listener. If you should mishear John Fogerty’s “There’s a bad moon on the rise” as “There’s a bathroom on the right,” so be it. From the perspective of evolution, the speech system, which works most of the time, is good enough, and that’s all that matters.
Curmudgeons of every generation think that their children and grandchildren don’t speak properly. Ogden Nash put it this way in 1962, in “Laments for a Dying Language”:
Words in computer languages are fixed in meaning, but words in human languages change constantly; one generation’s
Part of the answer stems from how our
Take, for example, what might happen if you were walking through the Redwood Forest and saw a tree trunk; odds are, you would conclude that you were looking at a tree, even if that trunk happened to be so tall that you couldn’t make out any leaves above. This habit of making snap judgments based on incomplete evidence (no leaves, no roots, just a trunk, and still we conclude we’ve seen a tree) is something we might call a logic of “partial matching.”
The logical antithesis, of course, would be to wait until we’d seen the whole thing; call that a logic of “full matching.” As you can imagine, he who waits until he’s seen the whole tree would never be wrong, but also risks missing a lot of bona fide foliage. Evolution rewarded those who were swift to decide, not those who were too persnickety to act.
For better or worse, language inherited this system wholesale. You might think of a chair, for instance, as something with four legs, a back, and a horizontal surface for sitting. But as the philosopher Ludwig Wittgenstein (1889-1951) realized, few concepts are really defined with such precision. Beanbag chairs, for example, are still considered chairs, even though they have neither an articulated back nor any sort of legs.
I call my cup of water a glass even though it’s made of plastic; I call my boss the chair of my department even though so far as I can tell she merely sits in one. A linguist or phylogenist uses the word
Another idiosyncrasy of language, considerably more subtle, has to do with words like
The peculiar thing is that in addition to quantifiers, we have another whole system that does something similar. This second system traffics in what linguists call “generics,” somewhat vague, generally accurate statements, such as
Generics are a whole different ball game, in many ways much less precise than quantifiers. It’s just not clear how many dogs have to have four legs before the statement
Computer-programming languages admit no such imprecision; they have ways of representing formal quantifiers ([DO THIS THING REPEATEDLY UNTIL EVERY DATABASE RECORD HAS BEEN EXAMINED]
) but no way of expressing generics at all. Human languages are idiosyncratic — and verging on redundant — inasmuch as they routinely exploit both systems, generics and the more formal quantifiers.
Why do we have both systems? Sarah-Jane Leslie, a young Princeton philosopher, has suggested one possible answer. The split between generics and quantifiers may reflect the divide in our reasoning capacity, between a sort of fast, automatic system on the one hand and a more formal, deliberative system on the other. Formal quantifiers rely on our deliberative system (which, when we are being careful, allows us to reason logically), while generics draw on our ancestral reflexive system. Generics are, she argues, essentially a linguistic realization of our older, less formal cognitive systems. Intriguingly, our sense of generics is “loose” in a second way: we are prepared to accept as true generics like
Leslie further suggests that generics seem to be learned first in childhood, before formal quantifiers; moreover, they may have emerged earlier in the development of language. At least one contemporary language (Piraha, spoken in the Amazon Basin) appears to employ generics but not formal quantifiers. All of this suggests one more way in which the particular details of human languages depend on the idiosyncrasies of how our mind evolved.
For all that, I doubt many linguists would be convinced that language is truly a kluge. Words are one thing, sentences another; even if words are clumsy, what linguists really want to know about is
In the past several years, Noam Chomsky, the founder and leader of modern linguistics, has taken to arguing just that. In particular, Chomsky has wondered aloud whether language (by which he means mainly the syntax of sentences) might come close “to what some super-engineer would construct, given the conditions that the language faculty must satisfy.” As linguists like Tom Wasow and Shalom Lappin have pointed out, there is