does not adequately enforce the necessity of the conclusion; otherwise, if the premises be granted, nothing whatever can be said against the inference of the conclusion. And here is another statement which seems not less wonderful, but on the premises assumed is equally necessary.”

“What is that?”

“The wicked are happier in undergoing punishment than if no penalty of justice chasten them. And I am not now meaning what might occur to anyone⁠—that bad character is amended by retribution, and is brought into the right path by the terror of punishment, or that it serves as an example to warn others to avoid transgression; but I believe that in another way the wicked are more unfortunate when they go unpunished, even though no account be taken of amendment, and no regard be paid to example.”

“Why, what other way is there beside these?” said I.

Then said she: “Have we not agreed that the good are happy, and the evil wretched?”

“Yes,” said I.

“Now, if,” said she, “to one in affliction there be given along with his misery some good thing, is he not happier than one whose misery is misery pure and simple without admixture of any good?”

“It would seem so.”

“But if to one thus wretched, one destitute of all good, some further evil be added besides those which make him wretched, is he not to be judged far more unhappy than he whose ill fortune is alleviated by some share of good?”

“It could scarcely be otherwise.”

“Surely, then, the wicked, when they are punished, have a good thing added to them⁠—to wit, the punishment which by the law of justice is good; and likewise, when they escape punishment, a new evil attaches to them in that very freedom from punishment which thou hast rightly acknowledged to be an evil in the case of the unrighteous.”

“I cannot deny it.”

“Then, the wicked are far more unhappy when indulged with an unjust freedom from punishment than when punished by a just retribution. Now, it is manifest that it is just for the wicked to be punished, and for them to escape unpunished is unjust.”

“Why, who would venture to deny it?”

“This, too, no one can possibly deny⁠—that all which is just is good, and, conversely, all which is unjust is bad.”

Then I answered: “These inferences do indeed follow from what we lately concluded; but tell me,” said I, “dost thou take no account of the punishment of the soul after the death of the body?”

“Nay, truly,” said she, “great are these penalties, some of them inflicted, I imagine, in the severity of retribution, others in the mercy of purification. But it is not my present purpose to speak of these. So far, my aim hath been to make thee recognise that the power of the bad which shocked thee so exceedingly is no power; to make thee see that those of whose freedom from punishment thou didst complain are never without the proper penalties of their unrighteousness; to teach thee that the license which thou prayedst might soon come to an end is not long-enduring; that it would be more unhappy if it lasted longer, most unhappy of all if it lasted forever; thereafter that the unrighteous are more wretched if unjustly let go without punishment than if punished by a just retribution⁠—from which point of view it follows that the wicked are afflicted with more severe penalties just when they are supposed to escape punishment.”

Then said I: “While I follow thy reasonings, I am deeply impressed with their truth; but if I turn to the common convictions of men, I find few who will even listen to such arguments, let alone admit them to be credible.”

“True,” said she; “they cannot lift eyes accustomed to darkness to the light of clear truth, and are like those birds whose vision night illumines and day blinds; for while they regard, not the order of the universe, but their own dispositions of mind, they think the license to commit crime, and the escape from punishment, to be fortunate. But mark the ordinance of eternal law. Hast thou fashioned thy soul to the likeness of the better, thou hast no need of a judge to award the prize⁠—by thine own act hast thou raised thyself in the scale of excellence; hast thou perverted thy affections to baser things, look not for punishment from one without thee⁠—thine own act hath degraded thee, and thrust thee down. Even so, if alternately thou turn thy gaze upon the vile earth and upon the heavens, though all without thee stand still, by the mere laws of sight thou seemest now sunk in the mire, now soaring among the stars. But the common herd regards not these things. What, then? Shall we go over to those whom we have shown to be like brute beasts? Why, suppose, now, one who had quite lost his sight should likewise forget that he had ever possessed the faculty of vision, and should imagine that nothing was wanting in him to human perfection, should we deem those who saw as well as ever blind? Why, they will not even assent to this, either⁠—that they who do wrong are more wretched than those who suffer wrong, though the proof of this rests on grounds of reason no less strong.”

“Let me hear these same reasons,” said I.

“Wouldst thou deny that every wicked man deserves punishment?”

“I would not, certainly.”

“And that those who are wicked are unhappy is clear in manifold ways?”

“Yes,” I replied.

“Thou dost not doubt, then, that those who deserve punishment are wretched?”

“Agreed,” said I.

“So, then, if thou wert sitting in judgment, on whom wouldst thou decree the infliction of punishment⁠—on him who had done the wrong, or on him who had suffered it?”

“Without doubt, I would compensate the sufferer at the cost of the doer of the wrong.”

“Then, the injurer would seem more wretched than the injured?”

“Yes; it follows. And so for this and other reasons resting on the same ground, inasmuch as baseness of its own nature makes men wretched, it

Вы читаете The Consolation of Philosophy
Добавить отзыв
ВСЕ ОТЗЫВЫ О КНИГЕ В ИЗБРАННОЕ

0

Вы можете отметить интересные вам фрагменты текста, которые будут доступны по уникальной ссылке в адресной строке браузера.

Отметить Добавить цитату