hunt or a battle, and so on) by musical means (choral singing); that 'description' is worked out polyphonically. The union of 'naturalistic'
imitation (which provides Janequin with some wonderful new sonorities) and erudite polyphony, a union, that is, of two nearly incompatible extremes, is fascinating: this is an art that is elegant, playful, joyous, and full of humor.
And yet: it is precisely the words 'elegant,' 'playful,' 'joyous,' 'humor,' that sentimental rhetoric sets in opposition to the profound. But what is profound and what is superficial? For Janequin's critic, superficial are the 'pictorial gifts' and 'description'; profound are the 'penetrating ardor in the expression of feelings' and the 'tones of tenderness, admiration, respect' for womankind. Thus 'profound' is what touches on the feelings. But one could define 'the profound' in another way: profound is what touches on the essential. The problem Janequin touches on in his compositions is the fundamental ontological problem of music: the problem of the relation between noise and musical sound.
Music and Noise
When man created a musical sound (by singing or by playing an instrument), he divided the acoustical world into two sharply distinct parts: that of artificial sounds and that of natural sounds. In his music, Janequin sought to put them together. In the middle of the sixteenth century, he thus prefigured what in the twentieth century would be done by, for instance, Janacek (his studies of spoken language), Bartok, or, in an extremely systematic way, Messiaen (in the works inspired by birdsong).
Janequin's art reminds us that there exists an acoustic universe outside the human soul, one that consists not merely of nature sounds but also of human voices speaking, singing, and giving sonic flesh to everyday life as well as to festive occasions. He reminds us that the composer can give a great musical form to that 'objective' universe.
One of Janacek's most original compositions:
I think of Stravinsky's
And I think of Bartok's piano suite
And I think, too, of the
I say, indeed: 'consolation in the nonsentience of nature.' For nonsentience is consoling; the world of nonsentience is the world outside human life; it is eternity; 'it is the sea gone off with the sun' (Rimbaud). I remember the gloomy years I spent in Bohemia early in the Russian occupation. I fell in love then with Varese and Xenakis: those pictures of sound-worlds that were objective but nonexistent spoke to me of a life freed of human subjectivity, aggressive and burdensome; they spoke of the sweetly nonhuman beauty of the world before or after mankind moved through it.
Melody
I listen to a polyphonic chant for two voices from the twelfth-century School of Notre-Dame in Paris: underneath, in augmented note values, as a
apart) has something marvelous about it: like reality and parable at once, here is the birth of European music as art: a melody is created to go in counterpoint with another, very old, melody whose origins are almost unknown; so this new one is there as something secondary, subordinate, it is there to
This old polyphonic composition delights me: the new melody on top is long, unending, and
And it's my impression that until Bach the art of melody would keep that quality the earliest polyphonic composers gave it. I listen to the Adagio of Bach's E Major Violin Concerto: like a kind of
The situation changes with the dawn of the Classical. Composition loses its polyphonic nature; in
the sonority of the accompaniment harmonies, the autonomy of the various singular voices disappears, and disappears still more as the great innovation of the second half-the symphonic orchestra with its thickness of sound-gains prominence; the melody that was 'secondary,' 'subordinate,' becomes the main point in composition and dominates musical structure, which incidentally undergoes a complete transformation.
Then the character of melody changes too: no more is it the long line that runs through an entire piece; it can be reduced to a phrase of a few measures, a phrase that is very expressive and concentrated, and thus easily memorizable, that can catch (or provoke) a direct emotion (more than ever before, music is set a great semantic task: to capture and musically 'describe' all the emotions and their nuances). This is why the present-day audience applies the term 'great melodist' to the composers of the second half-to a Mozart, a Chopin-but rarely to Bach or Vivaldi and still less to Josquin des Pres or Palestrina: the current idea of melody (of what constitutes beautiful melody) was shaped by the Classical aesthetic.
Yet it is not true that Bach is less melodic than Mozart; it is only that his melody is different.
is that kernel out of which (as Schoenberg said) the whole is created; but that is not the melodic treasure of
that arise from this theme and form the counterpoint to it. I like very much Hermann Scherchen's orchestration and recorded interpretation; for example, Contrapunctus IV, the